Plotinus, 204–270 CE |
“I haven't got time to read.”
“But you watch Match of the Day and East
Enders!”
Philosophy is not an easy subject.
Quite a lot of it has to do with epistemology – or the theory of knowledge. We
see the world as mediated through our senses, and are subject to suppositions
and presuppositions; our minds are clouded by a great deal that we were taught,
but which turns out not to be true; and the world is
discontinuous with our consciousness. How then can we be certain of anything?
Strictly, we cannot. Surprisingly, Jane Austen illustrates this perfectly in Emma: “Seldom, very seldom, does complete truth belong to any human
disclosure; seldom can it happen that something is not a little disguised, or a
little mistaken . . .” However, it is not particularly fruitful to be too
concerned with this, but healthier to note that philosophy asks questions:
often very tough questions that require hard thinking, and it is what is
learned on the way that matters, not the solving of the problem to everyone’s
satisfaction.
I am not too sure that philosophy
might thrive rather better than it does if parents were more open to the kinds
of questions that their children tend to ask:
“Daddy, what keeps the earth from
falling?”
“Don’t ask silly questions . . . where’s
your mother got to . . .”
Well, the Presocratic philosopher,
Anaximander, was deeply interested in this problem – as it was perceived at the
time – and he came up with a very ingenious answer:
There are some (including, among the
philosophers of long ago, Anaximander) who say that the earth stays where it is
because of equality. For something which is established in the centre and has
equality in relation to the extremes has no more reason to move up that it does
down or to the sides; it is impossible for it to move in
opposite directions at the same time, and so it is bound to stay where it is. (Aristotle, On the Heavens)
Robin Waterfield, the translator of The First Philosophers – from which this
extract is taken – writes in the introduction, “This is remarkable as an early
preference for theory over the evidence of the senses, where the two conflict;
for surely the senses would seem to confirm that nothing just hangs in place in
mid–air.”
It might be thought from the above
example that all philosophy will gradually become redundant, as science answers
more and more of the questions that philosophy poses. But I do not think this
will be so. You might as well say that science will eventually replace poetry.
But poetry, science, and philosophy are all separate entities (or activities).
Moreover, the business of science is not to answer the questions posed by philosophy. We are in need of another
example:
Plotinus has observed that every entity
aspires to the Good and believes itself to have achieved the highest state of
being when it participates in it; so long as one does not possess it, one
wishes for something else, but when one
possesses it, one wishes oneself: thus, being and willing coincide. (Maria Luisa Gatti, Plotinus: The Platonic tradition and the foundation of Neoplatonism. In the Cambridge Companion to Plotinus.)
Well, the language is not easy, and
we may well doubt that “every entity aspires to the Good.” However, the core
meaning seems to be that if we lived in accordance with the Good, and therefore
within the true bounds of our nature, we would not be restless in seeking those
things which are unnecessary to our wellbeing. I am sure that it is impossible
to fully realise such a state of being. Nonetheless, the idea is powerfully
suggestive. We tend to be plagued by all manner of idiocies, but this need not
be the case, if only we would think more deeply about things. Fiction, drama,
and film can and do teach us these lessons, but there is something in Maria Luisa
Gatti’s succinct exposition of this aspect of Plotinus’ thought that
concentrates the mind, and has universal applicability. And what she says is
echoed by another contributor to the same Oxford Companion, who refreshingly
quotes Wordsworth’s Ode: Intimations of
Immortality (as well as Yeats’ Sailing
to Byzantium):
Aesop’s fable of the dog who lost his real bone because he jealously required the
bone he saw reflected in the water would have appealed to Plotinus. We are “here”
because our souls mistook reflections for the Real, and our only escape is to
recall what truly is, and whence we
came.
Hence in a season of calm weather / Though inland far we be / Our souls have sight of that
immortal sea / Which
brought us hither.
(Stephen
R. L. Cark Plotinus: Plotinus:
Body and soul. In the Cambridge
Companion to Plotinus.)
It is not easy to “recall what truly
is, and whence we came.” And if we follow Kant, then we must accept that the
direct pursuit of happiness plays no part in the effort that must be made:
. . . the problem of determining
certainly and universally what action will promote the happiness of a rational
being is completely insoluble; and consequently . . . in regard to this there
is no imperative possible which in the strictest sense could command us to do
what will make us happy, since happiness is an Ideal, not of reason but of the
Imagination – an Ideal resting merely on empirical grounds, of which it is vain
to expect that they should determine an action by which we could attain the
totality of a series of consequences which is in fact infinite. (H. J. Paton, The Moral Law. Paton’s translation of Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals)
This is a complex passage – and it
should be said that the original German is so difficult – that many German
speaking scholars prefer to read Kant in English translation (some of his sentences
being of paragraph length, so that his series of “ifs” and “thens” need to
be underlined if they are to be grasped). There is more in this passage than I
can unravel, but the primary point – that we have no means of determining
precisely what will make us happy – seems sound. “Happiness is an incidental
blossoming” writes Aristotle, and so it is. Yet see how many lost souls queue
up to buy lottery tickets and scratch cards – thinking that a sudden access of
fortune will solve all their problems and make them happy.
Imagine that you pass a skip in the
road, and notice that it is full to overflowing with £50 notes. This is of course highly improbable,
but for the purposes of a thought experiment is unproblematic. Well, you do not have to be a philosopher
to realise that the money is not yours, and your first duty is to inform the
police. But, if you have studied philosophy – particularly, say, Aristotle or
Kant – then you will not even be tempted to take so much as a single note. You
will not say to yourself “no one will miss £50”– knowing that such
argumentation is utterly beside the point. Or, as Aristotle would express it:
“You cannot steal the right amount from the right person under the right
circumstances at the right time. Stealing is simply wrong.” Yet imagine the
pandemonium, fighting, and sheer greed that you would witness should the skip
be discovered by others before the police arrived!
______________________
______________________
Blog index
The index on Blogger does not work, so I'm creating an index to the blogs according to title, theme, subject. This can be found on my website:
No comments:
Post a Comment